Plato; or, The Philosopher
Ralph Waldo Emerson
Plato only is entitled to Omar's fanatical compliment to the Koran, when he
said, "Burn the libraries; for their value is in this book." These
sentences contain the culture of nations; these are the corner-stone of
schools; these are the fountain-head of literatures. A discipline it is in
logic, arithmetic, taste, symmetry, poetry, language, rhetoric, ontology,
morals or practical wisdom. There was never such range of speculation. Out of
Plato come all things that are still written and debated among men of
thought. Great havoc makes he among our originalities. We have reached the
mountain from which all these drift boulders were detached. The Bible of the
learned for twenty-two hundred years, every brisk young man who says in
succession fine things to each reluctant generation,- Boethius, Rabelais,
Erasmus, Bruno, Locke, Rousseau, Alfieri, Coleridge,- is some reader of
Plato, translating into the vernacular, wittily, his good things. Even the
men of grander proportion suffer some deduction from the misfortune (shall I
say?) of coming after this exhausting generalizer. St. Augustine, Copernicus,
Newton, Behmen, Swedenborg, Goethe, are likewise his debtors and must say
after him. For it is fair to credit the broadest generalizer with all the
particulars deducible from his thesis.
Plato
is philosophy, and philosophy, Plato,- at once the glory and the shame of
mankind, since neither Saxon nor Roman have availed to add any idea to his
categories. No wife, no children had he, and the thinkers of all civilized
nations are his posterity and are tinged with his mind. How many great men
Nature is incessantly sending up out of night, to be his men,- Platonists!
the Alexandrians, a constellation of genius; the Elizabethans, not less; Sir
Thomas More, Henry More, John Hales, John Smith, Lord Bacon, Jeremy Taylor,
Ralph Cudworth, Sydenham, Thomas Taylor; Marcilius Ficinus and Picus Mirandola.
Calvinism is in his Phaedo: Christianity is in it. Mahometanism draws all its
philosophy, in its hand-book of morals, the Akhlak-y-Jalaly, from him. Mysticism
finds in Plato all its texts. This citizen of a town in Greece is no villager
nor patriot. An Englishman reads and says, "how English!" a German-
"how Teutonic!" an Italian- "how Roman and how Greek!" As
they say that Helen of Argos had that universal beauty that every body felt
related to her, so Plato seems to a reader in New England an American genius.
His broad humanity transcends all sectional lines.
This
range of Plato instructs us what to think of the vexed question concerning
his reputed works,- what are genuine, what spurious. It is singular that
wherever we find a man higher by a whole head than any of his contemporaries,
it is sure to come into doubt what are his real works. Thus Homer, Plato,
Raffaelle, Shakespeare. For these men magnetize their contemporaries, so that
their companions can do for them what they can never do for themselves; and
the great man does thus live in several bodies, and write, or paint or act,
by many hands; and after some time it is not easy to say what is the
authentic work of the master and what is only of his school.
Plato,
too, like every great man, consumed his own times. What is a great man but
one of great affinities, who takes up into himself all arts, sciences, all
knowables, as his food? He can spare nothing; he can dispose of every thing. What
is not good for virtue, is good for knowledge. Hence his contemporaries tax
him with plagiarism. But the inventor only knows how to borrow; and society
is glad to forget the innumerable laborers who ministered to this architect,
and reserves all its gratitude for him. When we are praising Plato, it seems
we are praising quotations from Solon and Sophron and Philolaus. Be it so. Every
book is a quotation; and every house is a quotation out of all forests and
mines and stone quarries; and every man is a quotation from all his
ancestors. And this grasping inventor puts all nations under contribution.
Plato
absorbed the learning of his times,- Philolaus, Timaeus, Heraclitus,
Parmenides, and what else; then his master, Socrates; and finding himself
still capable of a larger synthesis,- beyond all example then or since,- he
traveled into Italy, to gain what Pythagoras had for him; then into Egypt,
and perhaps still farther East, to import the other element, which Europe
wanted, into the European mind. This breadth entitles him to stand as the
representative of philosophy. He says, in the Republic, "Such a genius
as philosophers must of necessity have, is wont but seldom in all its parts
to meet in one man, but its different parts generally spring up in different
persons." Every man who would do anything well, must come to it from a
higher ground. A philosopher must be more than a philosopher. Plato is
clothed with the powers of a poet, stands upon the highest place of the poet,
and (though I doubt he wanted the decisive gift of lyric expression), mainly
is not a poet because he chose to use the poetic gift to an ulterior purpose.
Great
geniuses have the shortest biographies. Their cousins can tell you nothing
about them. They lived in their writings, and so their house and street life
was trivial and commonplace. If you would know their tastes and complexions,
the most admiring of their readers most resembles them. Plato especially has
no external biography. If he had lover, wife, or children, we hear nothing of
them. He ground them all into paint. As a good chimney burns its smoke, so a
philosopher converts the value of all his fortunes into his intellectual
performances.
He
was born 427 A.C., about the time of the death of Pericles; was of patrician
connection in his times and city, and is said to have had an early inclination
for war, but, in his twentieth year, meeting with Socrates, was easily
dissuaded from this pursuit and remained for ten years his scholar, until the
death of Socrates. He then went to Megara, accepted the invitations of Dion
and of Dionysius to the court of Sicily, and went thither three times, though
very capriciously treated. He traveled into Italy; then into Egypt, where he
stayed a long time; some say three,- some say thirteen years. It is said he
went farther, into Babylonia: this is uncertain. Returning to Athens, he gave
lessons in the Academy to those whom his fame drew thither; and died, as we
have received it, in the act of writing, at eighty-one years.
But
the biography of Plato is interior. We are to account for the supreme
elevation of this man in the intellectual history of our race,- how it
happens that in proportion to the culture of men they become his scholars;
that, as our Jewish Bible has implanted itself in the tabletalk and household
life of every man and woman in the European and American nations, so the
writings of Plato have preoccupied every school of learning, every lover of
thought, every church, every poet,- making it impossible to think, on certain
levels, except through him. He stands between the truth and every man's mind,
and has almost impressed language and the primary forms of thought with his
name and seal. I am struck, in reading him, with the extreme modernness of
his style and spirit. Here is the germ of that Europe we know so well, in its
long history of arts and arms; here are all its traits, already discernible
in the mind of Plato,- and in none before him. It has spread itself since
into a hundred histories, but has added no new element. This perpetual
modernness is the measure of merit in every work of art; since the author of
it was not misled by any thing short-lived or local, but abode by real and
abiding traits. How Plato came thus to be Europe, and philosophy, and almost
literature, is the problem for us to solve.
This
could not have happened without a sound, sincere and catholic man, able to
honor, at the same time, the ideal, or laws of the mind, and fate, or the
order of nature. The first period of a nation, as of an individual, is the
period of unconscious strength. Children cry, scream and stamp with fury,
unable to express their desires. As soon as they can speak and tell their
want and the reason of it, they become gentle. In adult life, whilst the
perceptions are obtuse, men and women talk vehemently and superlatively,
blunder and quarrel: their manners are full of desperation; their speech is
full of oaths. As soon as, with culture, things have cleared up a little, and
they see them no longer in lumps and masses but accurately distributed, they
desist from that weak vehemence and explain their meaning in detail. If the
tongue had not been framed for articulation, man would still be a beast in
the forest. The same weakness and want, on a higher plane, occurs daily in
the education of ardent young men and women. "Ah! you don't understand
me; I have never met with any one who comprehends me": and they sigh and
weep, write verses and walk alone,- fault of power to express their precise
meaning. In a month or two, through the favor of their good genius, they meet
some one so related as to assist their volcanic estate, and, good
communication being once established, they are thenceforward good citizens. It
is ever thus. The progress is to accuracy, to skill, to truth, from blind
force.
There
is a moment in the history of every nation, when, proceeding out of this
brute youth, the perceptive powers reach their ripeness and have not yet
become microscopic: so that man, at that instant, extends across the entire
scale, and, with his feet still planted on the immense forces of night,
converses by his eyes and brain with solar and stellar creation. That is the
moment of adult health, the culmination of power.
Such
is the history of Europe, in all points; and such in philosophy. Its early
records, almost perished, are of the immigrations from Asia, bringing with
them the dreams of barbarians; a confusion of crude notions of morals and of
natural philosophy, gradually subsiding through the partial insight of single
teachers.
Before
Pericles came the Seven Wise Masters, and we have the beginnings of geometry,
metaphysics and ethics: then the partialists,- deducing the origin of things
from flux or water, or from air, or from fire, or from mind. All mix with
these causes mythologic pictures. At last comes Plato, the distributor, who
needs no barbaric point, or tattoo, or whooping; for he can define. He leaves
with Asia the vast and superlative; he is the arrival of accuracy and
intelligence. "He shall be as a god to me, who can rightly divide and
define."
This
defining is philosophy. Philosophy is the account which the human mind gives
to itself of the constitution of the world. Two cardinal facts lie forever at
the base; the one, and the two: 1. Unity, or Identity; and, 2. Variety. We
unite all things by perceiving the law which pervades them; by perceiving the
superficial differences and the profound resemblances. But every mental act,-
this very perception of identity or oneness, recognizes the difference of
things. Oneness and otherness. It is impossible to speak or to think without
embracing both.
The
mind is urged to ask for one cause of many effects; then for the cause of
that; and again the cause, diving still into the profound: self-assured that
it shall arrive at an absolute and sufficient one,- a one that shall be all. "In
the midst of the sun is the light, in the midst of the light is truth, and in
the midst of truth is the imperishable being," say the Vedas. All
philosophy, of East and West, has the same centripetence. Urged by an
opposite necessity, the mind returns from the one to that which is not one,
but other or many; from cause to effect; and affirms the necessary existence
of variety, the self-existence of both, as each is involved in the other. These
strictly-blended elements it is the problem of thought to separate and to
reconcile. Their existence is mutually contradictory and exclusive; and each
so fast slides into the other that we can never say what is one, and what it
is not. The Proteus is as nimble in the highest as in the lowest grounds;
when we contemplate the one, the true, the good,- as in the surfaces and
extremities of matter.
In
all nations there are minds which incline to dwell in the conception of the
fundamental Unity. The raptures of prayer and ecstasy of devotion lose all
being in one Being. This tendency finds its highest expression in the
religious writings of the East, and chiefly in the Indian Scriptures, in the
Vedas, the Bhagavat Geeta, and the Vishnu Purana. Those writings contain
little else than this idea, and they rise to pure and sublime strains in celebrating
it.
The
Same, the Same: friend and foe are of one stuff; the ploughman, the plough
and the furrow are of one stuff; and the stuff is such and so much that the
variations of form are unimportant. "You are fit" (says the supreme
Krishna to a sage) "to apprehend that you are not distinct from me. That
which I am, thou art, and that also is this world, with its gods and heroes
and mankind. Men contemplate distinctions, because they are stupefied with
ignorance." "The words I and mine constitute ignorance. What is the
great end of all, you shall now learn from me. It is soul,- one in all
bodies, pervading, uniform, perfect, preeminent over nature, exempt from
birth, growth and decay, omnipresent, made up of true knowledge, independent,
unconnected with unrealities, with name, species and the rest, in time past,
present and to come. The knowledge that this spirit, which is essentially
one, is in one's own and in all other bodies, is the wisdom of one who knows
the unity of things. As one diffusive air, passing through the perforations
of a flute, is distinguished as the notes of a scale, so the nature of the
Great Spirit is single, though its forms be manifold, arising from the
consequences of acts. When the difference of the investing form, as that of
god or the rest, is destroyed, there is no distinction." "The whole
world is but a manifestation of Vishnu, who is identical with all things, and
is to be regarded by the wise as not differing from, but as the same as
themselves. I neither am going nor coming; nor is my dwelling in any one
place; nor art thou, thou; nor are others, others; nor am I, I." As if
he had said, "All is for the soul, and the soul is Vishnu; and animals
and stars are transient paintings; and light is whitewash; and durations are
deceptive; and form is imprisonment; and heaven itself a decoy." That
which the soul seeks is resolution into being above form, out of Tartarus and
out of heaven,- liberation from nature.
If
speculation tends thus to a terrific unity, in which all things are absorbed,
action tends directly backwards to diversity. The first is the course or
gravitation of mind; the second is the power of nature. Nature is the
manifold. The unity absorbs, and melts or reduces. Nature opens and creates. These
two principles reappear and interpenetrate all things, all thought; the one,
the many. One is being; the other, intellect: one is necessity; the other,
freedom: one, rest; the other, motion: one, power; the other, distribution:
one, strength; the other, pleasure: one, consciousness; the other,
definition: one, genius; the other, talent: one, earnestness; the other,
knowledge: one, possession; the other, trade: one, caste; the other, culture:
one, king; the other, democracy: and, if we dare carry these generalizations
a step higher, and name the last tendency of both, we might say, that the end
of the one is escape from organization,- pure science; and the end of the
other is the highest instrumentality, or use of means, or executive deity.
Each
student adheres, by temperament and by habit, to the first or to the second
of these gods of the mind. By religion, he tends to unity; by intellect, or
by the senses, to the many. A too rapid unification, and an excessive
appliance to parts and particulars, are the twin dangers of speculation.
To
this partiality the history of nations corresponded. The country of unity, of
immovable institutions, the seat of a philosophy delighting in abstractions,
of men faithful in doctrine and in practice to the idea of a deaf,
unimplorable, immense fate, is Asia; and it realizes this faith in the social
institution of caste. On the other side, the genius of Europe is active and
creative: it resists caste by culture; its philosophy was a discipline; it is
a land of arts, inventions, trade, freedom. If the East loved infinity, the
West delighted in boundaries.
European
civility is the triumph of talent, the extension of system, the sharpened
understanding, adaptive skill, delight in forms, delight in manifestation, in
comprehensible results. Pericles, Athens, Greece, had been working in this
element with the joy of genius not yet chilled by any foresight of the
detriment of an excess. They saw before them no sinister political economy;
no ominous Malthus; no Paris or London; no pitiless subdivision of classes,-
the doom of the pin-makers, the doom of the weavers, of dressers, of
stockingers, of carders, of spinners, of colliers; no Ireland; no Indian
caste, superinduced by the efforts of Europe to throw it off. The
understanding was in its health and prime. Art was in its splendid novelty. They
cut the Pentelican marble as if it were snow, and their perfect works in
architecture and sculpture seemed things of course, not more difficult than
the completion of a new ship at the Medford yards, or new mills at Lowell. These
things are in course, and may be taken for granted. The Roman legion,
Byzantine legislation, English trade, the saloons of Versailles, the cafes of
Paris, the steam-mill, steamboat, steam-coach, may all be seen in
perspective; the town-meeting, the ballot-box, the newspaper and cheap press.
Meantime,
Plato, in Egypt and in Eastern pilgrimages, imbibed the idea of one Deity, in
which all things are absorbed. The unity of Asia and the detail of Europe;
the infinitude of the Asiatic soul and the defining, result-loving,
machine-making, surface-seeking, opera-going Europe,- Plato came to join,
and, by contact, to enhance the energy of each. The excellence of Europe and
Asia are in his brain. Metaphysics and natural philosophy expressed the
genius of Europe; he substructs the religion of Asia, as the base.
In
short, a balanced soul was born, perceptive of the two elements. It is as
easy to be great as to be small. The reason why we do not at once believe in
admirable souls is because they are not in our experience. In actual life,
they are so rare as to be incredible; but primarily there is not only no
presumption against them, but the strongest presumption in favor of their
appearance. But whether voices were heard in the sky, or not; whether his mother
or his father dreamed that the infant man-child was the son of Apollo;
whether a swarm of bees settled on his lips, or not;- a man who could see two
sides of a thing was born. The wonderful synthesis so familiar in nature; the
upper and the under side of the medal of Jove; the union of impossibilities,
which reappears in every object; its real and its ideal power,- was now also
transferred entire to the consciousness of a man.
The
balanced soul came. If he loved abstract truth, he saved himself by propounding
the most popular of all principles, the absolute good, which rules rulers,
and judges the judge. If he made transcendental distinctions, he fortified
himself by drawing all his illustrations from sources disdained by orators
and polite conversers; from mares and puppies; from pitchers and soup-ladles;
from cooks and criers; the shops of potters, horse-doctors, butchers and
fishmongers. He cannot forgive in himself a partiality, but is resolved that
the two poles of thought shall appear in his statement. His argument and his
sentence are self-imposed and spherical. The two poles appear; yes, and
become two hands, to grasp and appropriate their own.
Every
great artist has been such by synthesis. Our strength is transitional,
alternating; or, shall I say, a thread of two strands. The sea-shore, sea
seen from shore, shore seen from sea; the taste of two metals in contact; and
our enlarged powers at the approach and at the departure of a friend; the
experience of poetic creativeness, which is not found in staying at home, nor
yet in traveling, but in transitions from one to the other, which must
therefore be adroitly managed to present as much transitional surface as
possible; this command of two elements must explain the power and the charm
of Plato. Art expresses the one or the same by the different. Thought seeks
to know unity in unity; poetry to show it by variety; that is, always by an
object or symbol. Plato keeps the two vases, one of aether and one of
pigment, at his side, and invariably uses both. Things added to things, as
statistics, civil history, are inventories. Things used as language are
inexhaustibly attractive. Plato turns incessantly the obverse and the reverse
of the medal of Jove.
To
take an example:- The physical philosophers had sketched each his theory of
the world; the theory of atoms, of fire, of flux, of spirit; theories
mechanical and chemical in their genius. Plato, a master of mathematics,
studious of all natural laws and causes, feels these, as second causes, to be
no theories of the world but bare inventories and lists. To the study of
nature he therefore prefixes the dogma,- "Let us declare the cause which
led the Supreme Ordainer to produce and compose the universe. He was good;
and he who is good has no kind of envy. Exempt from envy, he wished that all
things should be as much as possible like himself. Whosoever, taught by wise
men, shall admit this as the prime cause of the origin and foundation of the
world, will be in the truth." "All things are for the sake of the
good, and it is the cause of every thing beautiful." This dogma animates
and impersonates his philosophy.
The
synthesis which makes the character of his mind appears in all his talents. Where
there is great compass of wit, we usually find excellencies that combine
easily in the living man, but in description appear incompatible. The mind of
Plato is not to be exhibited by a Chinese catalogue, but is to be apprehended
by an original mind in the exercise of its original power. In him the freest
abandonment is united with the precision of a geometer. His daring
imagination gives him the more solid grasp of facts; as the birds of highest
flight have the strongest alar bones. His patrician polish, his intrinsic
elegance, edged by an irony so subtle that it stings and paralyzes, adorn the
soundest health and strength of frame. According to the old sentence,
"If Jove should descend to the earth, he would speak in the style of
Plato."
With
this palatial air there is, for the direct aim of several of his works and
running through the tenor of them all, a certain earnestness, which mounts,
in the Republic and in the Phaedo, to piety. He has been charged with
feigning sickness at the time of the death of Socrates. But the anecdotes
that have come down from the times attest his manly interference before the
people in his master's behalf, since even the savage cry of the assembly to
Plato is preserved; and the indignation towards popular government, in many
of his pieces, expresses a personal exasperation. He has a probity, a native
reverence for justice and honor, and a humanity which makes him tender for
the superstitions of the people. Add to this, he believes that poetry,
prophecy and the high insight are from a wisdom of which man is not master;
that the gods never philosophize, but by a celestial mania these miracles are
accomplished. Horsed on these winged steeds, he sweeps the dim regions,
visits worlds which flesh cannot enter; he saw the souls in pain, he hears
the doom of the judge, he beholds the penal metempsychosis, the Fates, with
the rock and shears, and hears the intoxicating hum of their spindle.
But
his circumspection never forsook him. One would say he had read the
inscription on the gates of Busyrane,- "Be bold"; and on the second
gate,- "Be bold, be bold, and evermore be bold"; and then again had
paused well at the third gate,- "Be not too bold." His strength is
like the momentum of a falling planet, and his discretion the return of its
due and perfect curve,- so excellent is his Greek love of boundary and his
skill in definition. In reading logarithms one is not more secure than in
following Plato in his flights. Nothing can be colder than his head, when the
lightnings of his imagination are playing in the sky. He has finished his
thinking before he brings it to the reader, and he abounds in the surprises
of a literary master. He has that opulence which furnishes, at every turn,
the precise weapon he needs. As the rich man wears no more garments, drives
no more horses, sits in no more chambers than the poor,- but has that one
dress, or equipage, or instrument, which is fit for the hour and the need; so
Plato, in his plenty, is never restricted, but has the fit word. There is
indeed no weapon in all the armory of wit which he did not possess and use,-
epic, analysis, mania, intuition, music, satire and irony, down to the
customary and polite. His illustrations are poetry and his jests
illustrations. Socrates' profession of obstetric art is good philosophy; and
his finding that word "cookery," and "adulatory art," for
rhetoric, in the Gorgias, does us a substantial service still. No orator can
measure in effect with him who can give good nicknames.
What
moderation and understatement and checking his thunder in mid volley! He has
good-naturedly furnished the courtier and citizen with all that can be said
against the schools. "For philosophy is an elegant thing, if any one
modestly meddles with it; but if he is conversant with it more than is
becoming, it corrupts the man." He could well afford to be generous,-
he, who from the sunlike centrality and reach of his vision, had a faith
without cloud. Such as his perception, was his speech: he plays with the doubt
and makes the most of it: he paints and quibbles; and by and by comes a
sentence that moves the sea and land. The admirable earnest comes not only at
intervals, in the perfect yes and no of the dialogue, but in bursts of light.
"I, therefore, Callicles, am persuaded by these accounts, and consider
how I may exhibit my soul before the judge in a healthy condition. Wherefore,
disregarding the honors that most men value, and looking to the truth, I
shall endeavor in reality to live as virtuously as I can; and when I die, to
die so. And I invite all other men, to the utmost of my power; and you too I
in turn invite to this contest, which, I affirm, surpasses all contests
here."
He
is a great average man; one who, to the best thinking, adds a proportion and
equality in his faculties, so that men see in him their own dreams and
glimpses made available and made to pass for what they are. A great
common-sense is his warrant and qualification to be the world's interpreter. He
has reason, as all the philosophic and poetic class have: but he has also
what they have not,- this strong solving sense to reconcile his poetry with
the appearances of the world, and build a bridge from the streets of cities
to the Atlantis. He omits never this graduation, but slopes his thought,
however picturesque the precipice on one side, to an access from the plain. He
never writes in ecstasy, or catches us up into poetic raptures.
Plato
apprehended the cardinal facts. He could prostrate himself on the earth and
cover his eyes whilst he adored that which cannot be numbered, or gauged, or
known, or named: that of which every thing can be affirmed and denied: that
"which is entity and nonentity." He called it super-essential. He
even stood ready, as in the Parmenides, to demonstrate that it was so,- that
this Being exceeded the limits of intellect. No man ever more fully
acknowledged the Ineffable. Having paid his homage, as for the human race, to
the Illimitable, he then stood erect, and for the human race affirmed,
"And yet things are knowable!"- that is, the Asia in his mind was
first heartily honored,- the ocean of love and power, before form, before
will, before knowledge, the Same, the Good, the One; and now, refreshed and
empowered by this worship, the instinct of Europe, namely, culture, returns;
and he cries, "Yet things are knowable!" They are knowable, because
being from one, things correspond. There is a scale; and the correspondence
of heaven to earth, of matter to mind, of the part to the whole, is our
guide. As there is a science of stars, called astronomy; a science of
quantities, called mathematics; a science of qualities, called chemistry; so
there is a science of sciences,- I call it Dialectic,- which is the Intellect
discriminating the false and the true. It rests on the observation of
identity and diversity; for to judge is to unite to an object the notion
which belongs to it. The sciences, even the best,- mathematics and astronomy,-
are like sportsmen, who seize whatever prey offers, even without being able
to make any use of it. Dialectic must teach the use of them. "This is of
that rank that no intellectual man will enter on any study for its own sake,
but only with a view to advance himself in that one sole science which
embraces all."
"The
essence or peculiarity of man is to comprehend a whole; or that which in the
diversity of sensations can be comprised under a rational unity." "The
soul which has never perceived the truth, cannot pass into the human
form." I announce to men the Intellect. I announce the good of being
interpenetrated by the mind that made nature: this benefit, namely, that it
can understand nature, which it made and maketh. Nature is good, but
intellect is better: as the lawgiver is before the law-receiver. I give you
joy, O sons of men! that truth is altogether wholesome; that we have hope to
search out what might be the very self of everything. The misery of man is to
be baulked of the sight of essence and to be stuffed with conjectures; but
the supreme good is reality; the supreme beauty is reality; and all virtue
and all felicity depend on this science of the real: for courage is nothing
else than knowledge; the fairest fortune that can befall man is to be guided
by his daemon to that which is truly his own. This also is the essence of
justice,- to attend every one his own: nay, the notion of virtue is not to be
arrived at except through direct contemplation of the divine essence. Courage
then for "the persuasion that we must search that which we do not know,
will render us, beyond comparison, better, braver and more industrious than
if we thought it impossible to discover what we do not know, and useless to
search for it." He secures a position not to be commanded, by his
passion for reality; valuing philosophy only as it is the pleasure of
conversing with real being.
Thus,
full of the genius of Europe, he said, Culture. He saw the institutions of
Sparta and recognized, more genially one would say than any since, the hope
of education. He delighted in every accomplishment, in every graceful and
useful and truthful performance; above all in the splendors of genius and
intellectual achievement. "The whole of life, O Socrates," said
Glauco, "is, with the wise, the measure of hearing such discourses as
these." What a price he sets on the feats of talent, on the powers of
Pericles, of Isocrates, of Parmenides! What price above price on the talents
themselves! He called the several faculties, gods, in his beautiful
personation. What value he gives to the art of gymnastic in education; what
to geometry; what to music; what to astronomy, whose appeasing and medicinal
power he celebrates! In the Timaeus he indicates the highest employment of
the eyes. "By us it is asserted that God invented and bestowed sight on
us for this purpose,- that on surveying the circles of intelligence in the heavens,
we might properly employ those of our own minds, which, though disturbed when
compared with the others that are uniform, are still allied to their
circulations; and that having thus learned, and being naturally possessed of
a correct reasoning faculty, we might, by imitating the uniform revolutions
of divinity, set right our own wanderings and blunders." And in the
Republic,- "By each of these disciplines a certain organ of the soul is
both purified and reanimated which is blinded and buried by studies of
another kind; an organ better worth saving than ten thousand eyes, since
truth is perceived by this alone."
He
said, Culture; but he first admitted its basis, and gave immeasurably the
first place to advantages of nature. His patrician tastes laid stress on the
distinctions of birth. In the doctrine of the organic character and
disposition is the origin of caste. "Such as were fit to govern, into
their composition the informing Deity mingled gold; into the military,
silver; iron and brass for husbandmen and artificers." The East confirms
itself, in all ages, in this faith. The Koran is explicit on this point of
caste. "Men have their metal, as of gold and silver. Those of you who
were the worthy ones in the state of ignorance, will be the worthy ones in
the state of faith, as soon as you embrace it." Plato was not less firm.
"Of the five orders of things, only four can be taught to the generality
of men." In the Republic he insists on the temperaments of the youth, as
first of the first.
A
happier example of the stress laid on nature is in the dialogue with the
young Theages, who wishes to receive lessons from Socrates. Socrates declares
that if some have grown wise by associating with him, no thanks are due to
him; but, simply, whilst they were with him they grew wise, not because of
him; he pretends not to know the way of it. "It is adverse to many, nor
can those be benefited by associating with me whom the Daemon opposes; so
that it is not possible for me to live with these. With many however he does
not prevent me from conversing, who yet are not at all benefited by
associating with me. Such, O Theages, is the association with me; for, if it
pleases the God, you will make great and rapid proficiency: you will not, if
he does not please. Judge whether it is not safer to be instructed by some
one of those who have power over the benefit which they impart to men, than
by me, who benefit or not, just as it may happen." As if he had said,
"I have no system. I cannot be answerable for you. You will be what you
must. If there is love between us, inconceivably delicious and profitable
will our intercourse be; if not, your time is lost and you will only annoy
me. I shall seem to you stupid, and the reputation I have, false. Quite above
us, beyond the will of you or me, is this secret affinity or repulsion laid. All
my good is magnetic, and I educate, not by lessons, but by going about my
business."
He
said, Culture; he said, Nature; and he failed not to add, "There is also
the divine." There is no thought in any mind but it quickly tends to
convert itself into a power and organizes a huge instrumentality of means. Plato,
lover of limits, loved the illimitable, saw the enlargement and nobility
which come from truth itself and good itself, and attempted as if on the part
of the human intellect, once for all to do it adequate homage,- homage fit
for the immense soul to receive, and yet homage becoming the intellect to
render. He said then, "Our faculties run out into infinity, and return
to us thence. We can define but a little way; but here is a fact which will
not be skipped, and which to shut our eyes upon is suicide. All things are in
a scale; and, begin where we will, ascend and ascend. All things are
symbolical; and what we call results are beginnings."
A
key to the method and completeness of Plato is his twice bisected line. After
he has illustrated the relation between the absolute good and true and the
forms of the intelligible world, he says: "Let there be a line cut in
two unequal parts. Cut again each of these two main parts,- one representing
the visible, the other the intelligible world,- and let these two new
sections represent the bright part and the dark part of each of these worlds.
You will have, for one of the sections of the visible world, images, that is,
both shadows and reflections;- for the other section, the objects of these
images, that is, plants, animals, and the works of art and nature. Then
divide the intelligible world in like manner; the one section will be of
opinions and hypotheses, and the other section of truths." To these four
sections, the four operations of the soul correspond,- conjecture, faith,
understanding, reason. As every pool reflects the image of the sun, so every
thought and thing restores us an image and creature of the supreme Good. The
universe is perforated by a million channels for his activity. All things
mount and mount.
All
his thought has this ascension; in Phaedrus, teaching that beauty is the most
lovely of all things, exciting hilarity and shedding desire and confidence
through the universe wherever it enters, and it enters in some degree into
all things:- but that there is another, which is as much more beautiful than
beauty as beauty is than chaos; namely, wisdom, which our wonderful organ of
sight cannot reach unto, but which, could it be seen, would ravish us with
its perfect reality. He has the same regard to it as the source of excellence
in works of art. When an artificer, he says, in the fabrication of any work,
looks to that which always subsists according to the same; and, employing a
model of this kind, expresses its idea and power in his work,- it must follow
that his production should be beautiful. But when he beholds that which is
born and dies, it will be far from beautiful.
Thus
ever: the Banquet is a teaching in the same spirit, familiar now to all the
poetry and to all the sermons of the world, that the love of the sexes is
initial, and symbolizes at a distance the passion of the soul for that
immense lake of beauty it exists to seek. This faith in the Divinity is never
out of mind, and constitutes the ground of all his dogmas. Body cannot teach
wisdom;- God only. In the same mind he constantly affirms that virtue cannot
be taught; that it is not a science, but an inspiration; that the greatest
goods are produced to us through mania and are assigned to us by a divine
gift.
This
leads me to that central figure which he has established in his Academy as
the organ through which every considered opinion shall be announced, and
whose biography he has likewise so labored that the historic facts are lost
in the light of Plato's mind. Socrates and Plato are the double star which
the most powerful instruments will not entirely separate. Socrates again, in
his traits and genius, is the best example of that synthesis which
constitutes Plato's extraordinary power. Socrates, a man of humble stem, but
honest enough; of the commonest history; of a personal homeliness so
remarkable as to be a cause of wit in others:- the rather that his broad good
nature and exquisite taste for a joke invited the sally, which was sure to be
paid. The players personated him on the stage; the potters copied his ugly
face on their stone jugs. He was a cool fellow, adding to his humor a perfect
temper and a knowledge of his man, be he who he might whom he talked with,
which laid the companion open to certain defeat in any debate,- and in debate
he immoderately delighted. The young men are prodigiously fond of him and
invite him to their feasts, whither he goes for conversation. He can drink,
too; has the strongest head in Athens; and after leaving the whole party
under the table, goes away as if nothing had happened, to begin new dialogues
with somebody that is sober. In short, he was what our country-people call an
old one.
He
affected a good many citizen-like tastes, was monstrously fond of Athens,
hated trees, never willingly went beyond the walls, knew the old characters,
valued the bores and philistines, thought every thing in Athens a little
better than anything in any other place. He was plain as a Quaker in habit
and speech, affected low phrases, and illustrations from cocks and quails,
soup-pans and sycamore-spoons, grooms and farriers, and unnamable offices,-
especially if he talked with any superfine person. He had a Franklin-like
wisdom. Thus he showed one who was afraid to go on foot to Olympia, that it
was no more than his daily walk within doors, if continuously extended, would
easily reach.
Plain
old uncle as he was, with his great ears, an immense talker,- the rumor ran
that on one or two occasions, in the war with Boeotia, he had shown a
determination which had covered the retreat of a troop; and there was some
story that under cover of folly, he had, in the city government, when one day
he chanced to hold a seat there, evinced a courage in opposing singly the
popular voice, which had well-nigh ruined him. He is very poor; but then he
is hardy as a soldier, and can live on a few olives; usually, in the
strictest sense, on bread and water, except when entertained by his friends. His
necessary expenses were exceedingly small, and no one could live as he did. He
wore no under garment; his upper garment was the same for summer and winter,
and he went barefooted; and it is said that to procure the pleasure, which he
loves, of talking at his ease all day with the most elegant and cultivated
young men, he will now and then return to his shop and carve statues, good or
bad, for sale. However that be, it is certain that he had grown to delight in
nothing else than this conversation; and that, under his hypocritical
pretence of knowing nothing, he attacks and brings down all the fine
speakers, all the fine philosophers of Athens, whether natives or strangers
from Asia Minor and the islands. Nobody can refuse to talk with him, he is so
honest and really curious to know; a man who was willingly confuted if he did
not speak the truth, and who willingly confuted others asserting what was
false; and not less pleased when confuted than when confuting; for he thought
not any evil happened to men of such a magnitude as false opinion respecting
the just and unjust. A pitiless disputant, who knows nothing, but the bounds
of whose conquering intelligence no man had ever reached; whose temper was
imperturbable; whose dreadful logic was always leisurely and sportive; so
careless and ignorant as to disarm the wariest and draw them, in the
pleasantest manner, into horrible doubts and confusion. But he always knew
the way out; knew it, yet would not tell it. No escape; he drives them to
terrible choices by his dilemmas, and tosses the Hippiases and Gorgiases with
their grand reputations, as a boy tosses his balls. The tyrannous realist!- Meno
has discoursed a thousand times, at length, on virtue, before many companies,
and very well, as it appeared to him; but at this moment he cannot even tell
what it is,- this cramp-fish of a Socrates has so bewitched him.
This
hard-headed humorist, whose strange conceits, drollery and bonhommie diverted
the young patricians, whilst the rumor of his sayings and quibbles gets
abroad every day,- turns out, in the sequel, to have a probity as invincible
as his logic, and to be either insane, or at least, under cover of this play,
enthusiastic in his religion. When accused before the judges of subverting
the popular creed, he affirms the immortality of the soul, the future reward
and punishment; and refusing to recant, in a caprice of the popular
government was condemned to die, and sent to the prison. Socrates entered the
prison and took away all ignominy from the place, which could not be a prison
whilst he was there. Crito bribed the jailer; but Socrates would not go out
by treachery. "Whatever inconvenience ensue, nothing is to be preferred
before justice. These things I hear like pipes and drums, whose sound makes
me deaf to every thing you say." The fame of this prison, the fame of
the discourses there and the drinking of the hemlock are one of the most
precious passages in the history of the world.
The
rare coincidence, in one ugly body, of the droll and the martyr, the keen
street and market debater with the sweetest saint known to any history at
that time, had forcibly struck the mind of Plato, so capacious of these
contrasts; and the figure of Socrates by a necessity placed itself in the
foreground of the scene, as the fittest dispenser of the intellectual
treasures he had to communicate. It was a rare fortune that this Aesop of the
mob and this robed scholar should meet, to make each other immortal in their
mutual faculty. The strange synthesis in the character of Socrates capped the
synthesis in the mind of Plato. Moreover by this means he was able, in the
direct way and without envy to avail himself of the wit and weight of
Socrates, to which unquestionably his own debt was great; and these derived
again their principal advantage from the perfect art of Plato.
It
remains to say that the defect of Plato in power is only that which results
inevitably from his quality. He is intellectual in his aim; and therefore, in
expression, literary. Mounting into heaven, diving into the pit, expounding
the laws of the state, the passion of love, the remorse of crime, the hope of
the parting soul,- he is literary, and never otherwise. It is almost the sole
deduction from the merit of Plato that his writings have not,- what is no
doubt incident to this regnancy of intellect in his work,- the vital
authority which the screams of prophets and the sermons of unlettered Arabs
and Jews possess. There is an interval; and to cohesion, contact is
necessary.
I
know not what can be said in reply to this criticism but that we have come to
a fact in the nature of things: an oak is not an orange. The qualities of
sugar remain with sugar, and those of salt with salt.
In
the second place, he has not a system. The dearest defenders and disciples
are at fault. He attempted a theory of the universe, and his theory is not
complete or self-evident. One man thinks he means this, and another that; he has
said one thing in one place, and the reverse of it in another place. He is
charged with having failed to make the transition from ideas to matter. Here
is the world, sound as a nut, perfect, not the smallest piece of chaos left,
never a stitch nor an end, not a mark of haste, or botching, or second
thought; but the theory of the world is a thing of shreds and patches.
The
longest wave is quickly lost in the sea. Plato would willingly have a
Platonism, a known and accurate expression for the world, and it should be
accurate. It shall be the world passed through the mind of Plato,- nothing
less. Every atom shall have the Platonic tinge; every atom, every relation or
quality you knew before, you shall know again and find here, but now ordered;
not nature, but art. And you shall feel that Alexander indeed overran, with
men and horses, some countries of the planet; but countries, and things of
which countries are made, elements, planet itself, laws of planet and of men,
have passed through this man as bread into his body, and become no longer
bread, but body: so all this mammoth morsel has become Plato. He has clapped
copyright on the world. This is the ambition of individualism. But the
mouthful proves too large. Boa constrictor has good will to eat it, but he is
foiled. He falls abroad in the attempt; and biting, gets strangled: the
bitten world holds the biter fast by his own teeth. There he perishes:
unconquered nature lives on and forgets him. So it fares with all: so must it
fare with Plato. In view of eternal nature, Plato turns out to be
philosophical exercitations. He argues on this side and on that. The acutest
German, the lovingest disciple, could never tell what Platonism was; indeed,
admirable texts can be quoted on both sides of every great question from him.
These
things we are forced to say if we must consider the effort of Plato or of any
philosopher to dispose of nature,- which will not be disposed of. No power of
genius has ever yet had the smallest success in explaining existence. The
perfect enigma remains. But there is an injustice in assuming this ambition
for Plato. Let us not seem to treat with flippancy his venerable name. Men,
in proportion to their intellect, have admitted his transcendent claims. The
way to know him is to compare him, not with nature, but with other men. How
many ages have gone by, and he remains unapproached! A chief structure of
human wit, like Karnac, or the medieval cathedrals, or the Etrurian remains,
it requires all the breath of human faculty to know it. I think it is
trueliest seen when seen with the most respect. His sense deepens, his merits
multiply, with study. When we say, Here is a fine collection of fables; or
when we praise the style, or the common sense, or arithmetic, we speak as
boys, and much of our impatient criticism of the dialectic, I suspect, is no
better.
The
criticism is like our impatience of miles, when we are in a hurry; but it is
still best that a mile should have seventeen hundred and sixty yards. The
great-eyed Plato proportioned the lights and shades after the genius of our
life.
|